Advertisement

Requisites: the logic of intensions

  • Marie DužíEmail author
  • Bjørn Jespersen
  • Pavel Materna
Chapter
  • 460 Downloads
Part of the Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science book series (LEUS, volume 17)

Abstract

In Section 2.4.1 we argued in favour of semantic anti-actualism: the actual of all the possible worlds should play no semantic role. In this and the following sections we outline an essentialism that likewise accords no privileged status to the actual world by making the notion of essence independent of world and time and a priori instead .1 At the same time we are arguing in favour of ontological actualism: all the individuals at the actual world are all the individuals there are at all the other possible worlds as well (hence, there are no merely possible individuals, or possibilia).

Keywords

Actual World Natural Kind Tall Building Metaphysical Necessity Individual Office 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Partee, B. 2001. Privative adjectives: Subsective plus coercion. In Presupposition and Discourse, eds. R. Bäuerle, U. Reyle, and T.E. Zimmermann. Amsterdam: Elsevier. Accessible at http://people.umass.edu/partee/docs/ParteeInPressKampFest.pdf Google Scholar
  2. Stephanou, Y. 2000. Necessary beings. Analysis 60: 188–193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Marcus, R.B. 1993. Modalities. New York, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Jespersen, B. and P. Materna. 2002. Are wooden tables necessarily wooden? Acta Analytica 17: 115–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Rohrbaugh, G. and L. DeRosset. 2004. A new route to the necessity of origin. Mind 113: 705–725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Lange, M. 2004. A note on scientific essentialism, laws of nature, and counterfactual conditions. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 82: 227–241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Kripke, S. 1980. Naming and Necessity, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  8. Bergmann, G. 1967. Realism: A Critique of Brentano and Meinong. Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
  9. Bird, A. 2004. Strong necessitarianism: The nomological identity of possible worlds. Ratio 17: 256–276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Forbes, G. 1999. Enlightened semantics for simple sentences. Analysis 59: 86–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Zimmermann, T.E. 2005. What’s in two names? Journal of Semantics 22: 53–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Dretske, F. 1977. Laws of nature. Philosophy of Science 44: 248–268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Cameron, R.P. 2005. A note on Kripke’s footnote 56 argument for the essentiality of origin. Ratio 18: 262–275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Farrell, R. 1981. Metaphysical necessity is not logical necessity. Philosophical Studies 39: 141–153.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Tichý, P. 1984. Subjunctive conditionals: Two parameters vs. three. Philosophical Studies 45: 147–179. Reprinted in (Tichý 2004: 543–575).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Davies, M. and L. Humberstone. 1980. Two notions of necessity. Philosophical Studies 38: 1–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Barber, A. 2000. A pragmatic treatment of simple sentences. Analysis 60: 300–308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Moore, J. 1999. Saving substitutivity in simple sentences. Analysis 59: 91–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Tichý, P. 1983. Kripke on necessity a posteriori. Philosophical Studies 43: 225–241. Reprinted in (Tichý 2004: 507–523).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Rotstein, C. and Y. Winter. 2004. Total adjectives vs. partial adjectives: Scale structure and higher-order modifiers. Natural Language Semantics 12: 259–288.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Tichý, P. 1979. Existence and God. Journal of Philosophy 76: 403–420. Reprinted in (Tichý 2004: 353–372).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Hintikka, J. 1962. Knowledge and Belief: An Introduction to the Logic of the Two Notions. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  23. Plantinga, A. 1974. Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  24. Predelli, S. 2004. Superheroes and their names. American Philosophical Quarterly 41: 107–123.Google Scholar
  25. Cocchiarella, N.B. 1984. Philosophical perspectives on quantification in tense and modal logic. In Handbook of Philosophical Logic, vol. II, eds. D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner, 309–353. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Saul, J. 1997. Substitution and simple sentences. Analysis 57: 102–108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Pitt, D. 2001. Alter egos and their names. Journal of Philosophy 98: 531–552.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Spencer, C. 2006. Do conversational implicatures explain substitutivity failures? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 87: 126–139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Materna, P. 2005. Ordinary modalities. Logique et Analyse 48: 57–70.Google Scholar
  30. Mitchell, S.D. 2000. Dimensions of scientific law. Philosophy of Science 67: 291–302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Simchen, O. 2004. On the impossibility of nonactual epistemic possibilities. Journal of Philosophy 101: 527–554.Google Scholar
  32. Hughes, J. 2009. An artefact is to use: An introduction to instrumental functions. Synthese 168: 179–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Geach, P.T. 1956. Good and evil. Analysis 17: 33–42.Google Scholar
  34. Forbes, G. 1997. How much substitutivity? Analysis 57: 109–113.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010

Authors and Affiliations

  • Marie Duží
    • 1
    Email author
  • Bjørn Jespersen
    • 1
    • 2
    • 3
  • Pavel Materna
    • 4
    • 5
  1. 1.Fac. Electric Engineering and Computer Science, VSB-Technical University OstravaOstravaCzech Republic
  2. 2.Fac. Technology, Policy & Management, Delft University of TechnologyDelftNetherlands
  3. 3.Dept. LogicASCR Prague, Inst. PhilosophyPraha 1Czech Republic
  4. 4.Dept. LogicASCR Praha, Inst. PhilosophyPraha 1Czech Republic
  5. 5.Faculty of Informatics, Faculty of Arts, A. Nováka 1, Masaryk UniversityBrnoCzech Republic

Personalised recommendations